Filozofia nauki a historia nauki

2014
journal article
article
dc.abstract.enThe paper focuses on relations between philosophy of science and history of science. Two models of science are considered. The fi rst is provided by formal methodology (philosophy) of science. It assumes that (1) there exists an eff ective criterion of demarcation between science and non -science (in particular, pseudo -science); (2) science manifests itself in the same manner in all historical epochs; (3) science as a result (in particular, a system of propositions), not science as an activity, is the primary subject of philosophical investigations; (4) philosophy of science concentrates mostly on the context of justifi cation, not the context of discovery. Consequently, formal logic provides analytic devices for philosophy of science and history has a secondary importance. The second approach, the historical philosophy of science (or historicisms in the philosophy of science), denies the assumptions (1)-(4). Hence, the history of science is of the utmost importance for the philosophy of science. More specifi cally, history of science provides empirical data for the philosophy of science. As Imre Lakatos once said (it is a paraphrase of Kant) "Philosophy of science without history of science is empty, history of science without philosophy of science is blind". According to Lakatos, a rational reconstruction of the history of science constitutes the main task of the philosophy of science. The adjective "rational" indicates here that this reconstruction must be guided by principles elaborated by philosophical refl ection. Lakatos’s own proposal in this respect is captured by his famous idea of research programs as units organizing concrete scientifi c investigations and their development. The methodology of research programs is Lakatos’s answer to Kuhn’s philosophy of science as based on the concept of the paradigm of scientifi c activity accepted by scientists in a particular period. Lakatos objected that the acceptance of paradigms is, according to Kuhn, too irrational. In fact Lakatos wanted to combine Popper’s idea of the logic of scientifi c discover and Kuhn’s historicism. There are several objections to historicism. Disregarding one of the standard critical observations, namely that concerning the ambiguity of the terms "research program" and "paradigm", one can observe that the concepts of the external history of science and the internal history of science are unclear in philosophical theories of science off ered by Kuhn and Lakatos. Similar remarks apply to Paul Feyerabend’s rule "Everything goes" as admitt ing any methodology of scientifi c investigations. Since the representatives of historicism are almost exclusively interested in the internal history of science, they overlook the external history of science and blame it as naïve and consisting of popular stories concerning accidental circumstances related to great discoveries (Newton’s apple or killing of Archimedes). The author argues that this att itude is unjustifi ed. Clearly, any elaboration of the actual history is selective and thereby must appeal to some criteria of selection. On the other hand, too excessive use of philosophy in historical reconstruction converts history of science into historiosophy (speculative history) of science.pl
dc.abstract.plArtykuł analizuje relacje pomiędzy filozofią nauki i historią nauki. Rozważane są dwa podejścia do fi lozofi i nauki, jedno reprezentowane przez formalną metodologię nauk i drugie - przez historycznie zorientowaną teorię nauki. O ile pierwsza koncepcja traktuje historię nauki jako niezbyt istotną dla fi lozofi i nauki, orientacja druga uważa, że pierwsza jest kluczem do drugiej. Najlepiej wyraża to znane powiedzenie Imre Lakatosa: "Filozofi a nauki bez historii nauki jest pusta, historia nauki bez fi lozofi i nauki jest ślepa". Artykuł bliżej rozważa koncepcje Thomasa S. Kuhna i Imre Lakatosa jako sztandarowe wersje historycznej metodologii nauki. Autor argumentuje, że są to raczej historiozofi czne wizje nauki niż historie nauki.pl
dc.contributor.authorWoleński, Janpl
dc.date.accession2020-12-09pl
dc.date.accessioned2020-12-09T07:31:55Z
dc.date.available2020-12-09T07:31:55Z
dc.date.issued2014pl
dc.date.openaccess0
dc.description.accesstimew momencie opublikowania
dc.description.physical99-115pl
dc.description.versionostateczna wersja wydawcy
dc.description.volume13pl
dc.identifier.eissn2392-1749pl
dc.identifier.issn1731-6715pl
dc.identifier.projectROD UJ / OPpl
dc.identifier.urihttps://ruj.uj.edu.pl/xmlui/handle/item/258478
dc.identifier.weblinkhttp://pau.krakow.pl/PKHN-PAU/pkhn-pau-XIII-2014-6.pdfpl
dc.languagepolpl
dc.language.containerpolpl
dc.rightsUdzielam licencji. Uznanie autorstwa - Użycie niekomercyjne - Bez utworów zależnych 3.0 Polska*
dc.rights.licenceCC-BY-NC-ND
dc.rights.urihttp://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/pl/legalcode*
dc.share.typeotwarte czasopismo
dc.subject.enhistorypl
dc.subject.enphilosophy of sciencepl
dc.subject.enresearch programpl
dc.subject.enparadigmpl
dc.subject.plhistoriapl
dc.subject.plfilozofi a naukipl
dc.subject.plmetodologiapl
dc.subject.plprogram badawczypl
dc.subject.plparadygmatpl
dc.subtypeArticlepl
dc.titleFilozofia nauki a historia naukipl
dc.title.journalPrace Komisji Historii Nauki PAUpl
dc.typeJournalArticlepl
dspace.entity.typePublication
dc.abstract.enpl
The paper focuses on relations between philosophy of science and history of science. Two models of science are considered. The fi rst is provided by formal methodology (philosophy) of science. It assumes that (1) there exists an eff ective criterion of demarcation between science and non -science (in particular, pseudo -science); (2) science manifests itself in the same manner in all historical epochs; (3) science as a result (in particular, a system of propositions), not science as an activity, is the primary subject of philosophical investigations; (4) philosophy of science concentrates mostly on the context of justifi cation, not the context of discovery. Consequently, formal logic provides analytic devices for philosophy of science and history has a secondary importance. The second approach, the historical philosophy of science (or historicisms in the philosophy of science), denies the assumptions (1)-(4). Hence, the history of science is of the utmost importance for the philosophy of science. More specifi cally, history of science provides empirical data for the philosophy of science. As Imre Lakatos once said (it is a paraphrase of Kant) "Philosophy of science without history of science is empty, history of science without philosophy of science is blind". According to Lakatos, a rational reconstruction of the history of science constitutes the main task of the philosophy of science. The adjective "rational" indicates here that this reconstruction must be guided by principles elaborated by philosophical refl ection. Lakatos’s own proposal in this respect is captured by his famous idea of research programs as units organizing concrete scientifi c investigations and their development. The methodology of research programs is Lakatos’s answer to Kuhn’s philosophy of science as based on the concept of the paradigm of scientifi c activity accepted by scientists in a particular period. Lakatos objected that the acceptance of paradigms is, according to Kuhn, too irrational. In fact Lakatos wanted to combine Popper’s idea of the logic of scientifi c discover and Kuhn’s historicism. There are several objections to historicism. Disregarding one of the standard critical observations, namely that concerning the ambiguity of the terms "research program" and "paradigm", one can observe that the concepts of the external history of science and the internal history of science are unclear in philosophical theories of science off ered by Kuhn and Lakatos. Similar remarks apply to Paul Feyerabend’s rule "Everything goes" as admitt ing any methodology of scientifi c investigations. Since the representatives of historicism are almost exclusively interested in the internal history of science, they overlook the external history of science and blame it as naïve and consisting of popular stories concerning accidental circumstances related to great discoveries (Newton’s apple or killing of Archimedes). The author argues that this att itude is unjustifi ed. Clearly, any elaboration of the actual history is selective and thereby must appeal to some criteria of selection. On the other hand, too excessive use of philosophy in historical reconstruction converts history of science into historiosophy (speculative history) of science.
dc.abstract.plpl
Artykuł analizuje relacje pomiędzy filozofią nauki i historią nauki. Rozważane są dwa podejścia do fi lozofi i nauki, jedno reprezentowane przez formalną metodologię nauk i drugie - przez historycznie zorientowaną teorię nauki. O ile pierwsza koncepcja traktuje historię nauki jako niezbyt istotną dla fi lozofi i nauki, orientacja druga uważa, że pierwsza jest kluczem do drugiej. Najlepiej wyraża to znane powiedzenie Imre Lakatosa: "Filozofi a nauki bez historii nauki jest pusta, historia nauki bez fi lozofi i nauki jest ślepa". Artykuł bliżej rozważa koncepcje Thomasa S. Kuhna i Imre Lakatosa jako sztandarowe wersje historycznej metodologii nauki. Autor argumentuje, że są to raczej historiozofi czne wizje nauki niż historie nauki.
dc.contributor.authorpl
Woleński, Jan
dc.date.accessionpl
2020-12-09
dc.date.accessioned
2020-12-09T07:31:55Z
dc.date.available
2020-12-09T07:31:55Z
dc.date.issuedpl
2014
dc.date.openaccess
0
dc.description.accesstime
w momencie opublikowania
dc.description.physicalpl
99-115
dc.description.version
ostateczna wersja wydawcy
dc.description.volumepl
13
dc.identifier.eissnpl
2392-1749
dc.identifier.issnpl
1731-6715
dc.identifier.projectpl
ROD UJ / OP
dc.identifier.uri
https://ruj.uj.edu.pl/xmlui/handle/item/258478
dc.identifier.weblinkpl
http://pau.krakow.pl/PKHN-PAU/pkhn-pau-XIII-2014-6.pdf
dc.languagepl
pol
dc.language.containerpl
pol
dc.rights*
Udzielam licencji. Uznanie autorstwa - Użycie niekomercyjne - Bez utworów zależnych 3.0 Polska
dc.rights.licence
CC-BY-NC-ND
dc.rights.uri*
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/pl/legalcode
dc.share.type
otwarte czasopismo
dc.subject.enpl
history
dc.subject.enpl
philosophy of science
dc.subject.enpl
research program
dc.subject.enpl
paradigm
dc.subject.plpl
historia
dc.subject.plpl
filozofi a nauki
dc.subject.plpl
metodologia
dc.subject.plpl
program badawczy
dc.subject.plpl
paradygmat
dc.subtypepl
Article
dc.titlepl
Filozofia nauki a historia nauki
dc.title.journalpl
Prace Komisji Historii Nauki PAU
dc.typepl
JournalArticle
dspace.entity.type
Publication
Affiliations

* The migration of download and view statistics prior to the date of April 8, 2024 is in progress.

Views
32
Views per month
Views per city
Warsaw
10
Krakow
3
Wroclaw
3
Sosnowiec
2
Berlin
1
Bielany Wrocławskie
1
Dublin
1
Kocmyrzow
1
Lacko
1
Lublin
1
Downloads
wolenski_filozofia_nauki_a_historia_nauki_2014.pdf
31
wolenski_filozofia_nauki_a_historia_nauki_2014.odt
8